McFall v. Shimp and Thomson’s Violinist don’t justify the vast majority of abortions.

Many people argue that abortion is justified because of bodily rights. The idea is that it
doesn’t matter if the fetus is a person or not, because no person can use your body
against your will. If that principle is generally true and generally applies to
abortion, it makes sense to be pro-choice regardless of whether or not you think the
fetus is a valuable human.




McFall v. Shimp
People who argue that
bodily rights are paramount sometimes point to the court case of McFall v. Shimp. This isn’t a huge court case—it wasn’t the Supreme Court, it was the
Court of Common Pleas in Pennsylvania—but it’s an important case because of the
unique case elements.

Robert McFall was an
asbestos worker with anemia. He was given a 20% chance of surviving another
year unless he got a bone marrow transplant. His relatives were tested and his
cousin, David Shimp, was a likely match. Unfortunately Shimp didn’t want to
donate his bone marrow. In desperation McFall took Shimp to court, hoping to
compel Shimp to give this life-saving donation. However the court sided fairly
quickly with Shimp. The judge stated,


Morally, this decision rests with the Defendant, and, in the view of the Court,
the refusal of the Defendant is morally indefensible. For a law to compel the
Defendant to submit to an intrusion of his body would change every concept and
principle upon which our society is founded.

In other words, even
though Robert McFall was clearly a person with as much moral worth as you and
I, and even though he would die without this bodily donation, the Court would
not compel Shimp to donate to McFall. And McFall did die shortly thereafter.


Article here.

So if we can’t compel
someone to give of his body to save Robert McFall, how can we compel someone to give of her
body to save a fetus?



The Violinist
Another example of
this idea is a thought experiment by Judith Jarvis Thomson. She wrote an essay
called “A Defense of Abortion” in which she argued that we need not debate
whether the fetus is a person because abortion is justified anyway. To illustrate
her point, she asks you to imagine you wake up one day in a hospital bed and your
circulatory system is hooked up to a man in the bed next to you. You learn this
man is a very talented and famous violinist with a fatal kidney ailment, and his fans–the Society of Music Lovers–have somehow reviewed all
available medical records and learned that you are the
only person with the right kidney or blood type to filter the
poisons from the Violinist’s blood. So the Society of Music Lovers kidnaps you,
knocks you out, and attaches you to the Violinist.


The hospital director
enters the room and says he is terribly sorry—if he had realized what was
happening he would have never allowed it. Nevertheless, you’re now attached to
the Violinist and if you unplug, the man will die. But if you stay plugged in
for nine months, the Violinist will be cured and you can each go on your way.

Thomson then asks if
it is morally required of you to stay plugged in to the Violinist. And even if
it is morally required, should it be legally required? Most people intuitively
think it should not. They agree it would be a heroic act if you stayed hooked
up to the Violinist, but they don’t think such an act should be legally required.



True Analogies
I agree with both the
real life example of McFall v. Shimp and the hypothetical example of the
Violinist. I don’t think Shimp should have been legally required to donate to
McFall, and I don’t think you should be legally required to stay hooked up to the
Violinist. And yet I still think most abortions should be illegal. Is that a
contradiction?

No, it’s not.

McFall v. Shimp and
The Violinist are not analogous to abortion; if they were I would
think bodily donation should be required in those cases too.

In order for a bodily
rights argument to be analogous to abortion, the hypothetical needs to
include the following five elements:
  1. If you refuse bodily
    donation, someone else will die.
  2. You chose to risk
    making this person’s life depend on you.
  3. No one else can save
    this person.
  4. Your bodily donation
    is temporary.
  5. Your refusal means
    actively killing this person, not just neglecting to save him.

Some suggest
that last factor is being too nitpicky. If the person is going to be dead
either way, what difference does it make whether you neglect to save him versus actively kill him? 


It makes a great deal of difference.
It’s the difference between watching someone drown while refusing to try to rescue him versus holding him underwater until he dies. It’s the difference
between unplugging from the Violinist and letting him succumb to his kidney
ailment versus shooting him in the head. We recognize both socially and legally
a great difference between actively killing someone versus simply neglecting to
save him. And the main point here is that most forms of abortion actively kill
humans, rather than simply fail to save them.



McFall v. Shimp
Revisited
McFall v. Shimp does not meet all five criteria. It does have the following two elements:

  • If you refuse bodily donation, someone else will die.
  • Your bodily donation is temporary.

Shimp refused to donate bone marrow, and McFall died. And bone marrow donations are temporary in the sense that you can regenerate bone marrow. 


But the case lacks the remaining three criteria:

  • You chose to risk making this person’s life depend on you.
  • No one else can save this person.
  • Your refusal means actively killing this person, not just neglecting to save him.

Shimp had nothing to do with the fact that McFall’s life was in danger. (And even though Shimp was in no way responsible for McFall’s condition, the court still found Shimp’s refusal to donate “morally indefensible.”) Additionally, in coming to a ruling, the Court discussed the fact that there could be an unrelated person out there who was a bone marrow match. (If you’re interested in potentially saving lives through bone marrow donation, please check out BeTheMatch.org.) Finally, Shimp neglected to save McFall; he didn’t actively kill his cousin.

If McFall v. Shimp
were truly analogous to abortion, it would involve Shimp making a decision that he knew could endanger McFall. Say
there was some button Shimp could press that made him feel wonderful; he knew pushing the button involved the remote chance that
McFall would contract a fatal ailment only Shimp could save him from. Still, Shimp figured the chance was too small to worry about, and so he pushed the button anyway. Then McFall did get a fatal illness, and he reached out to Shimp
to save him. Shimp declined …and then shot McFall in the head.
That’s abortion.




The Violinist
Revisited
The Violinist thought
experiment suffers from similar limitations. It’s a bit closer to the proper
analogy because Thomson includes the fact that you
are the only person who can save the Violinist. So The Violinist has the three
elements: 

  • If you refuse bodily donation, someone else will die.
  • No one else can save this person.
  • Your bodily donation is temporary.
But the thought experiment fails to meet the remaining two criteria:

  • You chose to risk making this person’s life depend on you.
  • Your refusal means actively killing this person, not just neglecting to save him.

In the thought experiment, you didn’t
choose to risk the Violinist’s life, nor did you choose to hook yourself up to
him. In fact a major aspect of the story is that you were kidnapped and hooked up to the Violinist
against your will. You very specifically had no choice in the matter.
Furthermore you don’t kill the Violinist. You are choosing whether or not to
unplug from him and let him succumb to his ailment; you’re not choosing whether
to smother him with a pillow.


When bodily rights
arguments are adjusted to include all five criteria, they
become pretty unpersuasive. At best the conclusion sounds incredibly immoral, and at worst
it also sounds very illegal.



Roe v. Wade
It’s important to
also understand what the Supreme Court case legalizing abortion, Roe v. Wade,
had to say about bodily rights. During oral arguments they did argue that the
woman should be able to get an abortion because it’s her body and thus her
choice. However SCOTUS did not ground the right to abortion in bodily rights;
instead they grounded it in a right to privacy and explicitly rejected the bodily rights argument:

Click to enlarge
Roe v. Wade actually
ruled that the government can outlaw abortion after a certain point in the
pregnancy, meaning the government can compel bodily donation to keep another
alive. In fact in an article analyzing McFall v. Shimp and whether we should
always say bodily rights trump saving
lives, FE Huffman cites Roe v. Wade as precedent for compulsory bodily
donation.

Click to enlarge
Huffman also notes
that Roe v. Wade didn’t even consider the fetus a person and yet still allowed
for compulsory bodily donation to keep another entity alive. How much stronger
would the case be if the law recognized the fetus as a person?*


If your response to all this is that these analogies overstate the case because the fetus isn’t a person, you’re implicitly demonstrating my point: bodily rights arguments work only if the fetus isn’t a person. If the fetus is a valuable human being, the “my body, my choice” train of thought isn’t nearly strong enough to justify abortion.


We have now completed half of this cycle.

Consider the fact that most Americans believe abortion is justified only at earlier stages of pregnancy or only under more severe
circumstances. If you believe elective abortion should be illegal at later stages of the pregnancy, your stance implies bodily right are not sacrosanct. For people who view
the embryo and fetus as morally valuable humans from the beginning, bodily rights don’t even come
close to justifying the vast majority of abortions.

*During oral arguments the justices and plaintiffs suggested that if we recognized the
fetus as a person under the 14th amendment, it would be almost impossible to
justify legal abortion. Remember that background when people claim Roe v.
Wade remained neutral on the question of when life begins.





Further Reading
ERI Bodily Rights Materials – a whole collection of thoughtful articles by the Equal Rights Institute related to bodily rights arguments.

Misconceptions about the rape exception – Secular Pro-Life Perspectives, 7/19/14, post exploring the relationship between bodily rights arguments and the rape exception

Leave a Comment